Link Search Menu Expand Document

The Core Idea

According to a (modest) dual process theory, there are two (or more) mindreading processes which are distinct in this sense: the conditions which influence whether they occur, and which outputs they generate, do not completely overlap.

If the slides are not working, or you prefer them full screen, please try this link.

Notes

What Is a Two-Systems Theory? The Core Idea

In general, a modest two-systems theory concerning some cognitive domain (e.g. numerical cognition or moral cognition) claims just this:

Two (or more) processes which enable functioning in this domain are distinct: the conditions which influence whether they occur, and which outputs they generate, do not completely overlap.1

One process is faster than another: it makes fewer demands on scarce cognitive resources such as attention, inhibitory control and working memory.

A key feature of this two systems theory is its theoretical modesty: it involves no a priori commitments concerning the particular characteristics of the processes. Identifying characteristics of the process is a matter of discovery.

Further, their characteristics may vary across domains. The characteristics that distinguish processes involved in mindreading may not entirely overlap with those that distinguish processes involved in physical cognition, or in numerical cognition, or in moral cognition.

Minimal Illustration: Toxicity

What do you compute that enables you to track toxicity?

Option 2 (slow but accurate): measure molecular composition (feed it to shellfish and use liquid chromatography-mass spectrometry).

Option 1 (limited but fast): experience disgust …

‘Disgust is thought to have originated in distaste, a food-rejection impulse or motivation triggered by the ingestion of unpleasant-tasting substances, prototypically those that are bitter (Chapman, Kim, Susskind, & Anderson, 2009; Rozin & Fallon, 1987). Because many bitter substances are toxic (Garcia, Hankins, Denton, & Coghlan, 1975), the role of distaste in food rejection has a clear and concrete adaptive function. Distaste appears to have very ancient origins: Even sea anemones, which first evolved some 500 million years ago, will expel bitter foods from their gastric cavity (Garcia et al., 1975)’ (Chapman & Anderson, 2013, p. 300).

In Which Domains Are There Two-Systems Theories?

Two-systems theories of one kind or another have been proposed for various domains. Here is a partial list of domains (note that some domains may overlap):

There are also domains where it is arguably coherent to suppose that researchers have identified what might be called a two-systems theory although this terminology is not in common use:

Systems 1 and 2 ???

Two systems theories often make claims beyond the core idea:

‘Typically, one of the processes is characterized as fast, effortless, automatic, nonconscious, inflexible, heavily contextualized, and undemanding of working memory, and the other as slow, effortful, controlled, conscious, flexible, decontextualized, and demanding of working memory’ (Frankish & Evans, 2009, p. 1).

As several researchers have pointed out, this way of characterising systems goes beyond the evidence available and depends on assumptions about the characteristics coming in neat bundles (Adolphs, 2010; Keren & Schul, 2009).

There may also be reasons to doubt that bold hypotheses about these characteristics do much, if any, explanatory work (Butterfill, 2007; Butterfill, 2020).4

Dual-Process or Two-Systems?

Although two systems theories are sometimes understood as making claims over and above those of a dual-process theory (e.g. Gawronski et al., 2014), others do not make any distinction:

‘We use the term “system” only as a label for collections of cognitive processes that can be distinguished by their speed, their controllability, and the contents on which they operate’ (Kahneman & Frederick, 2005, p. 267).

We shall follow Kahneman in treating ‘Two-Systems’ and ‘Dual-Process’ as synonyms unless we encounter a need to distinguish them.

Glossary

automatic : On this course, a process is _automatic_ just if whether or not it occurs is to a significant extent independent of your current task, motivations and intentions. To say that _mindreading is automatic_ is to say that it involves only automatic processes. The term `automatic' has been used in a variety of ways by other authors: see Moors (2014, p. 22) for a one-page overview, Moors & De Houwer (2006) for a detailed theoretical review, or Bargh (1992) for a classic and very readable introduction
cognitively efficient : A process is cognitively efficient to the degree that it does not consume working memory and other scarce cognitive resources.
fast : A fast process is one that is to to some interesting degree cognitively efficient (and therefore likely also some interesting degree automatic). These processes are also sometimes characterised as able to yield rapid responses.
Since automaticity and cognitive efficiency are matters of degree, it is only strictly correct to identify some processes as faster than others.
The fast-slow distinction has been variously characterised in ways that do not entirely overlap (even individual author have offered differing characterisations at different times; e.g. Kahneman, 2013; Morewedge & Kahneman, 2010; Kahneman & Klein, 2009; Kahneman, 2002): as its advocates stress, it is a rough-and-ready tool rather than an element in a rigorous theory.
tracking an attribute : For a process to track an attribute is for the presence or absence of the attribute to make a difference to how the process unfolds, where this is not an accident. (And for a system or device to track an attribute is for some process in that system or device to track it.)
Tracking an attribute is contrasted with computing it. Unlike tracking, computing typically requires that the attribute be represented.

References

Adolphs, R. (2010). Conceptual challenges and directions for social neuroscience. Neuron, 65(6), 752–767. Retrieved from http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.006
Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116(4), 953–970.
Bargh, J. A. (1992). The Ecology of Automaticity: Toward Establishing the Conditions Needed to Produce Automatic Processing Effects. The American Journal of Psychology, 105(2), 181–199. https://doi.org/10.2307/1423027
Bicchieri, C. (2016). Norms in the wild: How to diagnose, measure, and change social norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Butterfill, S. A. (2007). What are modules and what is their role in development? Mind and Language, 22(4), 450–473.
Butterfill, S. A. (2020). The Developing Mind: A Philosophical Introduction. London: Routledge.
Chapman, H. A., & Anderson, A. K. (2013). Things rank and gross in nature: A review and synthesis of moral disgust. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 300–327. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0030964
Dayan, P., & Berridge, K. C. (2014). Model-based and model-free Pavlovian reward learning: Revaluation, revision, and revelation. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience, 14(2), 473–492. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13415-014-0277-8
Dickinson, A., & Pérez, O. D. (2018). Chapter 1 - Actions and Habits: Psychological Issues in Dual-System Theory. In R. Morris, A. Bornstein, & A. Shenhav (Eds.), Goal-Directed Decision Making (pp. 1–25). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-812098-9.00001-2
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2003). In two minds: Dual-process accounts of reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(10), 454–459. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2003.08.012
Feigenson, L., Dehaene, S., & Spelke, E. S. (2004). Core systems of number. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(7), 307–314. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.05.002
Frankish, K., & Evans, J. St. B. T. (2009). The duality of mind: An historical perspective. In J. St. B. T. Evans & K. Frankish (Eds.), In two minds: Dual processes and beyond (pp. 1–31). Oxford University Press.
Gawronski, B., Sherman, J. W., & Trope, Y. (2014). Two of what? A conceptual analysis of dual-process theories. In J. W. Sherman, B. Gawronski, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the social mind (pp. 3–19). New York: Guilford Press.
Gilbert, A. L., Regier, T., & Ivry, R. B. (2006). Whorf hypothesis is supported in the right visual field but not the left. PNAS, 103(2), 489–494.
Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences, 15(1), 20–25. https://doi.org/10.1016/0166-2236(92)90344-8
Greene, J. D. (2014). Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics. Ethics, 124(4), 695–726. https://doi.org/10.1086/675875
Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment. Neuron, 44(2), 389–400. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.027
Jackendoff, R. (2003). Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Jacoby, L. L. (1991). A process dissociation framework: Separating automatic from intentional uses of memory. Journal of Memory and Language, 30(5), 513–541. https://doi.org/10.1016/0749-596X(91)90025-F
Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: A perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. In T. Frangsmyr (Ed.), Le prix nobel, ed. T. Frangsmyr, 416–499. (Vol. 8, pp. 351–401). Stockholm, Sweden: Nobel Foundation.
Kahneman, D. (2013). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus; Giroux.
Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2005). A model of heuristic judgment. In K. J. Holyoak & R. G. Morrison (Eds.), The cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning (pp. 267–293). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). Conditions for intuitive expertise: A failure to disagree. American Psychologist, 64(6), 515–526. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0016755
Keren, G., & Schul, Y. (2009). Two is not always better than one. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4(6), 533–550. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6924.2009.01164.x
Kozhevnikov, M., & Hegarty, M. (2001). Impetus beliefs as default heuristics: Dissociation between explicit and implicit knowledge about motion. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 8(3), 439–453. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03196179
Moors, A. (2014). Examining the mapping problem in dual process models. In Dual process theories of the social mind (pp. 20–34). Guilford.
Moors, A., & De Houwer, J. (2006). Automaticity: A Theoretical and Conceptual Analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 132(2), 297–326. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.132.2.297
Morewedge, C. K., & Kahneman, D. (2010). Associative processes in intuitive judgment. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(10), 435–440. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2010.07.004
Sidarus, N., Vuorre, M., & Haggard, P. (2017). How action selection influences the sense of agency: An ERP study. NeuroImage, 150, 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2017.02.015
Sloman, S. (1996). The Empirical Case for Two Systems of Reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119(1), 3–22.
Todd, A. R., Cameron, C. D., & Simpson, A. (2016). Dissociating processes underlying level-1 visual perspective taking in adults. Cognition, in press.
Witzel, C., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2011). Is there a lateralized category effect for color? Journal of Vision, 11(12), 16. https://doi.org/10.1167/11.12.16

Endnotes

  1. Compare Frankish & Evans (2009, p. 1): ‘These theories come in different forms, but all agree in positing two distinct processing mechanisms for a given task, which employ different procedures and may yield different, and sometimes conflicting, results.’ 

  2. We have linked the sources to references chosen to be accessible and useful; these are not the first or canonical sources for two-systems theories. 

  3. Note that the balance of evidence may not currently support the Gilbert et al. (2006)’s findings (see Witzel & Gegenfurtner, 2011). 

  4. The bold hypotheses do, however, make dual-process theories readily falsifiable. As Gawronski et al. (2014, p. 11) note, ‘the number of events prohibited by dual-process theories—and thus their falsifiability—increases with the number of proposed covariations between dualities.’ As we will see in considering mindreading and physical cognition, there are other ways to ensure that a dual-process theory is readily falsifiable.